199 lines
9.3 KiB
C++
199 lines
9.3 KiB
C++
/*!
|
|
@file
|
|
Forward declares `boost::hana::Monad`.
|
|
|
|
@copyright Louis Dionne 2013-2016
|
|
Distributed under the Boost Software License, Version 1.0.
|
|
(See accompanying file LICENSE.md or copy at http://boost.org/LICENSE_1_0.txt)
|
|
*/
|
|
|
|
#ifndef BOOST_HANA_FWD_CONCEPT_MONAD_HPP
|
|
#define BOOST_HANA_FWD_CONCEPT_MONAD_HPP
|
|
|
|
#include <boost/hana/config.hpp>
|
|
|
|
|
|
BOOST_HANA_NAMESPACE_BEGIN
|
|
//! @ingroup group-concepts
|
|
//! @defgroup group-Monad Monad
|
|
//! The `Monad` concept represents `Applicative`s with the ability to
|
|
//! flatten nested levels of structure.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Historically, Monads are a construction coming from category theory,
|
|
//! an abstract branch of mathematics. The functional programming
|
|
//! community eventually discovered how Monads could be used to
|
|
//! formalize several useful things like side effects, which led
|
|
//! to the wide adoption of Monads in that community. However, even
|
|
//! in a multi-paradigm language like C++, there are several constructs
|
|
//! which turn out to be Monads, like `std::optional`, `std::vector` and
|
|
//! others.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Everybody tries to introduce `Monad`s with a different analogy, and
|
|
//! most people fail. This is called the [Monad tutorial fallacy][1]. We
|
|
//! will try to avoid this trap by not presenting a specific intuition,
|
|
//! and we will instead present what monads are mathematically.
|
|
//! For specific intuitions, we will let readers who are new to this
|
|
//! concept read one of the many excellent tutorials available online.
|
|
//! Understanding Monads might take time at first, but once you get it,
|
|
//! a lot of patterns will become obvious Monads; this enlightening will
|
|
//! be your reward for the hard work.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! There are different ways of defining a Monad; Haskell uses a function
|
|
//! called `bind` (`>>=`) and another one called `return` (it has nothing
|
|
//! to do with C++'s `return` statement). They then introduce relationships
|
|
//! that must be satisfied for a type to be a Monad with those functions.
|
|
//! Mathematicians sometimes use a function called `join` and another one
|
|
//! called `unit`, or they also sometimes use other category theoretic
|
|
//! constructions like functor adjunctions and the Kleisli category.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! This library uses a composite approach. First, we use the `flatten`
|
|
//! function (equivalent to `join`) along with the `lift` function from
|
|
//! `Applicative` (equivalent to `unit`) to introduce the notion of
|
|
//! monadic function composition. We then write the properties that must
|
|
//! be satisfied by a Monad using this monadic composition operator,
|
|
//! because we feel it shows the link between Monads and Monoids more
|
|
//! clearly than other approaches.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Roughly speaking, we will say that a `Monad` is an `Applicative` which
|
|
//! also defines a way to compose functions returning a monadic result,
|
|
//! as opposed to only being able to compose functions returning a normal
|
|
//! result. We will then ask for this composition to be associative and to
|
|
//! have a neutral element, just like normal function composition. For
|
|
//! usual composition, the neutral element is the identity function `id`.
|
|
//! For monadic composition, the neutral element is the `lift` function
|
|
//! defined by `Applicative`. This construction is made clearer in the
|
|
//! laws below.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! @note
|
|
//! Monads are known to be a big chunk to swallow. However, it is out of
|
|
//! the scope of this documentation to provide a full-blown explanation
|
|
//! of the concept. The [Typeclassopedia][2] is a nice Haskell-oriented
|
|
//! resource where more information about Monads can be found.
|
|
//!
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Minimal complete definitions
|
|
//! ----------------------------
|
|
//! First, a `Monad` must be both a `Functor` and an `Applicative`.
|
|
//! Also, an implementation of `flatten` or `chain` satisfying the
|
|
//! laws below for monadic composition must be provided.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! @note
|
|
//! The `ap` method for `Applicatives` may be derived from the minimal
|
|
//! complete definition of `Monad` and `Functor`; see below for more
|
|
//! information.
|
|
//!
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Laws
|
|
//! ----
|
|
//! To simplify writing the laws, we use the comparison between functions.
|
|
//! For two functions `f` and `g`, we define
|
|
//! @code
|
|
//! f == g if and only if f(x) == g(x) for all x
|
|
//! @endcode
|
|
//!
|
|
//! With the usual composition of functions, we are given two functions
|
|
//! @f$ f : A \to B @f$ and @f$ g : B \to C @f$, and we must produce a
|
|
//! new function @f$ compose(g, f) : A \to C @f$. This composition of
|
|
//! functions is associative, which means that
|
|
//! @code
|
|
//! compose(h, compose(g, f)) == compose(compose(h, g), f)
|
|
//! @endcode
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Also, this composition has an identity element, which is the identity
|
|
//! function. This simply means that
|
|
//! @code
|
|
//! compose(f, id) == compose(id, f) == f
|
|
//! @endcode
|
|
//!
|
|
//! This is probably nothing new if you are reading the `Monad` laws.
|
|
//! Now, we can observe that the above is equivalent to saying that
|
|
//! functions with the composition operator form a `Monoid`, where the
|
|
//! neutral element is the identity function.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Given an `Applicative` `F`, what if we wanted to compose two functions
|
|
//! @f$ f : A \to F(B) @f$ and @f$ g : B \to F(C) @f$? When the
|
|
//! `Applicative` `F` is also a `Monad`, such functions taking normal
|
|
//! values but returning monadic values are called _monadic functions_.
|
|
//! To compose them, we obviously can't use normal function composition,
|
|
//! since the domains and codomains of `f` and `g` do not match properly.
|
|
//! Instead, we'll need a new operator -- let's call it `monadic_compose`:
|
|
//! @f[
|
|
//! \mathtt{monadic\_compose} :
|
|
//! (B \to F(C)) \times (A \to F(B)) \to (A \to F(C))
|
|
//! @f]
|
|
//!
|
|
//! How could we go about implementing this function? Well, since we know
|
|
//! `F` is an `Applicative`, the only functions we have are `transform`
|
|
//! (from `Functor`), and `lift` and `ap` (from `Applicative`). Hence,
|
|
//! the only thing we can do at this point while respecting the signatures
|
|
//! of `f` and `g` is to set (for `x` of type `A`)
|
|
//! @code
|
|
//! monadic_compose(g, f)(x) = transform(f(x), g)
|
|
//! @endcode
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Indeed, `f(x)` is of type `F(B)`, so we can map `g` (which takes `B`'s)
|
|
//! on it. Doing so will leave us with a result of type `F(F(C))`, but what
|
|
//! we wanted was a result of type `F(C)` to respect the signature of
|
|
//! `monadic_compose`. If we had a joker of type @f$ F(F(C)) \to F(C) @f$,
|
|
//! we could simply set
|
|
//! @code
|
|
//! monadic_compose(g, f)(x) = joker(transform(f(x), g))
|
|
//! @endcode
|
|
//!
|
|
//! and we would be happy. It turns out that `flatten` is precisely this
|
|
//! joker. Now, we'll want our joker to satisfy some properties to make
|
|
//! sure this composition is associative, just like our normal composition
|
|
//! was. These properties are slightly cumbersome to specify, so we won't
|
|
//! do it here. Also, we'll need some kind of neutral element for the
|
|
//! composition. This neutral element can't be the usual identity function,
|
|
//! because it does not have the right type: our neutral element needs to
|
|
//! be a function of type @f$ X \to F(X) @f$ but the identity function has
|
|
//! type @f$ X \to X @f$. It is now the right time to observe that `lift`
|
|
//! from `Applicative` has exactly the right signature, and so we'll take
|
|
//! this for our neutral element.
|
|
//!
|
|
//! We are now ready to formulate the `Monad` laws using this composition
|
|
//! operator. For a `Monad` `M` and functions @f$ f : A \to M(B) @f$,
|
|
//! @f$ g : B \to M(C) @f$ and @f$ h : C \to M(D) @f$, the following
|
|
//! must be satisfied:
|
|
//! @code
|
|
//! // associativity
|
|
//! monadic_compose(h, monadic_compose(g, f)) == monadic_compose(monadic_compose(h, g), f)
|
|
//!
|
|
//! // right identity
|
|
//! monadic_compose(f, lift<M(A)>) == f
|
|
//!
|
|
//! // left identity
|
|
//! monadic_compose(lift<M(B)>, f) == f
|
|
//! @endcode
|
|
//!
|
|
//! which is to say that `M` along with monadic composition is a Monoid
|
|
//! where the neutral element is `lift`.
|
|
//!
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Refined concepts
|
|
//! ----------------
|
|
//! 1. `Functor`
|
|
//! 2. `Applicative` (free implementation of `ap`)\n
|
|
//! When the minimal complete definition for `Monad` and `Functor` are
|
|
//! both satisfied, it is possible to implement `ap` by setting
|
|
//! @code
|
|
//! ap(fs, xs) = chain(fs, [](auto f) {
|
|
//! return transform(xs, f);
|
|
//! })
|
|
//! @endcode
|
|
//!
|
|
//!
|
|
//! Concrete models
|
|
//! ---------------
|
|
//! `hana::lazy`, `hana::optional`, `hana::tuple`
|
|
//!
|
|
//!
|
|
//! [1]: https://byorgey.wordpress.com/2009/01/12/abstraction-intuition-and-the-monad-tutorial-fallacy/
|
|
//! [2]: https://wiki.haskell.org/Typeclassopedia#Monad
|
|
template <typename M>
|
|
struct Monad;
|
|
BOOST_HANA_NAMESPACE_END
|
|
|
|
#endif // !BOOST_HANA_FWD_CONCEPT_MONAD_HPP
|